УДК 329.12:373.44 Robert Nozick. WHY DO INTELLECTUALS OPPOSE CAPITALISM?
It is surprising that intellectuals oppose capitalism so. Other groups of comparable socio-economic status do not show the same degree of opposition in the same proportions. Statistically, then, intellectuals are an anomaly. Not all intellectuals are on the left. Like other groups, their opinions are spread along a curve. But in their case, the curve is shifted and skewed to the political left. By intellectuals, I do not mean all people of intelligence or of a certain level of education, but those who, in their vocation, deal with ideas as expressed in words, shaping the word flow others receive. These wordsmiths include poets, novelists, literary critics, newspaper and magazine journalists, and many professors. It does not include those who primarily produce and transmit quantitatively or mathematically formulated information or those working in visual media, painters, sculptors, cameramen. Unlike the wordsmiths, people in these occupations do not disproportionately oppose capitalism. The wordsmiths are concentrated in certain occupational sites: academia, the media, government bureaucracy. Wordsmith intellectuals fare well in capitalist society; there they have great freedom to formulate, encounter, and propagate new ideas, to read and discuss them. Their occupational skills are in demand, their income much above average. Why then do they disproportionately oppose capitalism? Indeed, some data suggest that the more prosperous and successful the intellectual, the more likely he is to oppose capitalism. This opposition to capitalism is mainly from the left but not solely so. Yeats, Eliot, and Pound opposed market society from the right. The opposition of wordsmith intellectuals to capitalism is a fact of social significance. They shape our ideas and images of society; they state the policy alternatives bureaucracies consider. From treatises to slogans, they give us the sentences to express ourselves. Their opposition matters, especially in a society that depends increasingly upon the explicit formulation and dissemination of information. We can distinguish two types of explanation for the relatively high proportion of intellectuals in opposition to capitalism. ✓ One type finds a factor unique to the anti-capitalist intellectuals. ✓ The second type of explanation identifies a factor applying to all intellectuals, a force propelling them toward anticapitalist views. Whether it pushes any particular intellectual over into anti-capitalism will depend upon the other forces acting upon him. In the aggregate, though, since it makes anti-capitalism more likely for each intellectual, such a factor will produce a larger proportion of anti-capitalist intellectuals. Our explanation will be of this second type. We will identify a factor which tilts intellectuals toward anti-capitalist attitudes but does not guarantee it in any particular case. Intellectuals feel they are the most valuable people, the ones with the highest merit, but a capitalist society does not satisfy the principle of distribution to each according to his merit.
The Value of IntellectualsIntellectuals now expect to be the most highly valued people in a society, those with the most prestige and power; those with the greatest rewards. Intellectuals feel entitled to this. But, by and large, a capitalist society does not honor its intellectuals. Ludwig von Mises explains the special resentment of intellectuals, in contrast to workers, by saying they mix socially with successful capitalists and so have them as a salient comparison group and are humiliated by their lesser status. However, even those intellectuals who do not mix socially are similarly resentful, while merely mixing is not enough - the sports and dancing instructors who cater to the rich and have affairs with them are not noticeably anti-capitalist. Why then do contemporary intellectuals feel entitled to the highest rewards their society has to offer and resentful when they do not receive this? Intellectuals feel they are the most valuable people, the ones with the highest merit, and that society should reward people in accordance with their value and merit. But a capitalist society does not satisfy the principle of distribution to each according to his merit or value. Apart from the gifts, inheritances, and gambling winnings that occur in a free society, the market distributes to those who satisfy the perceived market-expressed demands of others, and how much it so distributes depends on how much is demanded and how great the alternative supply is. Unsuccessful businessmen and workers do not have the same animus against the capitalist system as do the wordsmith intellectuals. Only the sense of unrecognized superiority, of entitlement betrayed, produces that animus. Why do wordsmith intellectuals think they are most valuable, and why do they think distribution should be in accordance with value? Note that this latter principle is not a necessary one. Other distributional patterns have been proposed, including equal distribution, distribution according to moral merit, distribution according to need. Indeed, there need not be any pattern of distribution a society is aiming to achieve, even a society concerned with justice. The justice of a distribution may reside in its arising from a just process of voluntary exchange of justly acquired property and services. Whatever outcome is produced by that process will be just, but there is no particular pattern the outcome must fit. Why, then, do wordsmiths view themselves as most valuable and accept the principle of distribution in accordance with value? From the beginnings of recorded thought, intellectuals have told us their activity is most valuable. Plato valued the rational faculty above courage and the appetites and deemed that philosophers should rule; Aristotle held that intellectual contemplation was the highest activity. It is not surprising that surviving texts record this high evaluation of intellectual activity. The people who formulated evaluations, who wrote them down with reasons to back them up, were intellectuals, after all. They were praising themselves. Those who valued other things more than thinking things through with words, whether hunting or power or uninterrupted sensual pleasure, did not bother to leave enduring written records. Only the intellectual worked out a theory of who was best. Tbe intellectual wants the whole society to be a school writ large, to be like the environment where he did so well and was so well appreciated.
The Schooling of IntellectualsWhat factor produced feelings of superior value on the part of intellectuals? I want to focus on one institution in particular: schools. As book knowledge became increasingly important, schooling - the education together in classes of young people in reading and book knowledge - spread. Schools became the major institution outside of the family to shape the attitudes of young people, and almost all those who later became intellectuals went through schools. There they were successful. They were judged against others and deemed superior. They were praised and rewarded, the teacher's favorites. How could they fail to see themselves as superior? Daily, they experienced differences in facility with ideas, in quick-wittedness. The schools told them, and showed them, they were better. The schools, too, exhibited and thereby taught the principle of reward in accordance with merit. To the intellectually meritorious went the praise, the teacher's smiles, and the highest grades. In the currency the schools had to offer, the smartest constituted the upper class. Though not part of the official curricula, in the schools the intellectuals learned the lessons of their own greater value in comparison with the others, and of how this greater value entitled them to greater rewards. The wider market society, however; taught a different lesson. There the greatest rewards did not go to the verbally brightest. There the intellectual skills were not most highly valued. Schooled in the lesson that they were most valuable, the most deserving of reward, the most entitled to reward, how could the intellectuals, by and large, fail to resent the capitalist society which deprived them of the just deserts to which their superiority entitled them? Is it surprising that what the schooled intellectuals felt for capitalist society was a deep and sullen animus that, although clothed with various publicly appropriate reasons, continued even when those particular reasons were shown to be inadequate? In saying that intellectuals feel entitled to the highest rewards the general society can offer, I do not mean that intellectuals hold these rewards to be the highest goods. Perhaps they value more the intrinsic rewards of intellectual activity or the esteem of the ages. Nevertheless, they also feel entitled to the highest appreciation from the general society, to the most and best it has to offer, paltry though that may be. I don't mean to emphasize especially the rewards that find their way into the intellectuals' pockets or even reach them personally. Identifying themselves as intellectuals, they can resent the fact that intellectual activity is not most highly valued and rewarded. The intellectual wants the whole society to be a school writ large, to be like the environment where he did so well and was so well appreciated. By incorporating standards of reward that are different from the wider society, the schools guarantee that some will experience downward mobility later. Those at the top of the school's hierarchy will feel entitled to a top position, not only in that micro-society but in the wider one, a society whose system they will resent when it fails to treat them according to their selfprescribed wants and entitlements. The school system thereby produces anti-capitalist feeling among intellectuals. Rather, it produces anti-capitalist feeling among verbal intellectuals. Why do the numbersmiths not develop the same attitudes as these wordsmiths? I conjecture that these quantitatively bright children, although they get good grades on the relevant examinations, do not receive the same face-to-face attention and approval from the teachers as do the verbally bright children. It is the verbal skills that bring these personal rewards from the teacher; and apparently it is these rewards that especially shape the sense of entitlement. Central Planning in the ClassroomThere is a further point to be added. The wordsmith intellectuals are successful within the formal, official social system of the schools, wherein the relevant rewards are distributed by the central authority of the teacher. The schools contain another informal social system within classrooms, hallways, and schoolyards, wherein rewards are distributed not by central direction but spontaneously at the pleasure and whim of schoolmates. Here the intellectuals do less well. It is not surprising, therefore, that distribution of goods and rewards via a centrally organized distributional mechanism later strikes intellectuals as more appropriate than the anarchy and chaos of the marketplace. For distribution in a centrally planned socialist society stands to distribution in a capitalist society as distribution by the teacher stands to distribution by the schoolyard and hallway. Our explanation does not postulate that intellectuals constitute a majority even of the academic upper class of the school. This group may consist mostly of those with substantial bookish skills along with social grace, strong motivation to please, friendliness, winning ways, and an ability to to play by the rules. Such pupils, too, will be highly regarded and rewarded by the teacher, and they will do extremely well in the wider society, as well. Our explanation hypothesizes that intellectuals are disproportionately represented in that portion of the schools' upper class that will experience relative downward mobility. Or, rather, in the group that predicts for itself a declining future. The animus will arise before the move into the wider world and the experience of an actual decline in status, at the point when the clever pupil realizes he will fare less well in the wider society than in his current school situation. This unintended consequence of the school system, the anti-capitalist animus of intellectuals, is, of course, reinforced when pupils read or are taught by intellectuals who present those very anti-capitalist attitudes. No doubt, some wordsmith intellectuals were cantankerous and questioning pupils and so were disapproved of by their teachers. Did they too learn the lesson that the best should get the highest rewards and think, despite their teachers, that they themselves were best and so start with an early resentment against the school system's distribution? Clearly, on this and the other issues discussed here, we need data on the school experiences of future wordsmith intellectuals to refine and test our hypotheses. Stated as a general point, it is hardly contestable that the norms within schools will affect the normative beliefs of people after they leave the schools. The schools, after all, are the major non-familial society that children learn to operate in, and hence schooling constitutes their preparation for the larger non-familial society. It is not surprising that those successful by the norms of a school system should resent a society, adhering to different norms, which does not grant them the same success. Nor, when those are the very ones who go on to shape a society's selfimage, its evaluation of itself, is it surprising when the society's verbally responsive portion turns against it. If you were designing a society, you would not seek to design it so that the wordsmiths, with all their influence, were schooled into animus against the norms of the society. Our explanation of the disproportionate anti-capitalism of intellectuals is based upon a very plausible sociological generalization.
Notice that this is not a deterministic law. Not all those who experience downward social mobility will turn against the system. Such downward mobility, though, is a factor which tends to produce effects in that direction, and so will show itself in differing proportions at the aggregate level. We might distinguish ways an upper class can move down: it can get less than another group or it can tie, failing to get more than those previously deemed lower. It is the first type of downward mobility which especially rankles and outrages; the second type is far more tolerable. Many intellectuals favor equality while only a small number call for an aristocracy of intellectuals. Our hypothesis speaks of the first type of downward mobility as especially productive of resentment and animus. The wordsmith intellectuals are successful within the fonnal, official social system of the schools, wherein the relevant rewards are distributed by the central authority of the teacher.
The school system imparts and rewards only some skills relevant to later success so its reward system will differ from that of the wider society. This guarantees that some, in moving to the wider society, will experience downward social mobility and its attendant consequences. Earlier I said that intellectuals want the society to be the schools writ large. Now we see that the resentment due to a frustrated sense of entitlement stems from the fact that the schools are not the society writ small. Our explanation now seems to predict the resentment of schooled intellectuals against their society whatever its nature, whether capitalist or communist. Clearly, then, data about the attitudes of intellectuals within communist countries toward apparatchiks would be relevant; will those intellectuals feel animus toward that system? Our hypothesis needs to be refined so that it does not apply to every society. Must the school systems in every society inevitably produce anti-societal animus in the intellectuals who do not receive that society's highest rewards? Probably not. A capitalist society is peculiar in that it seems to announce that it is open and responsive only to talent, individual initiative, personal merit. Growing up in an inherited caste or feudal society creates no expectation that reward will or should be in accordance with personal value. Despite the created expectation, a capitalist society rewards people only insofar as they serve the market-expressed desires of others; it rewards in accordance with economic contribution, not in accordance with personal value. However, it comes close enough to rewarding in accordance with value - value and contribution will very often be intermingled - so as to nurture the expectation produced by the schools. The ethos of the wider society is close enough to that of the schools so that the nearness creates resentment. Capitalist societies reward individual accomplishment or announce they do, and so they leave the intellectual, who considers himself most accomplished, particularly bitter. Another factor, I think, plays a role. Schools will tend to produce such anti-capitalist attitudes the more d1ey are attended together by a diversity of people. When almost all of those who will be economically successful are attending separate schools, the intellectuals will not have acquired that attitude of being superior to them. But even if many children of d1e upper class attend separate schools, an open society will have other schools that also include many who will become economically successful as entrepreneurs, and the intellectuals later will resentfully remember how superior they were academically to their peers who advanced more richly and powerfully. The openness of the society has another consequence, as well. The pupils, future wordsmiths and others, will not know how they will fare in the future. They can hope for anything. A society closed to advancement destroys those hopes early. In an open capitalist society, the pupils are not resigned early to limits on their advancement and social mobility, the society seems to announce that the most capable and valuable will rise to the very top, their schools have already given the academically most gifted the message that they are most valuable and deserving of the greatest rewards, and later these very pupils with the highest encouragement and hopes see others of their peers, whom they know and saw to be less meritorious, rising higher than they themselves, taking the foremost rewards to which they themselves felt themselves entitled. Is it any wonder they bear that society an animus? Some Further HypothesesWe have refined the hypothesis somewhat. It is not simply formal schools but formal schooling in a specified social context that produces anti-capitalist animus in intellectuals. No doubt, the hypothesis requires further refining. But enough. It is time to turn the hypothesis over to the social scientists, to take it from armchair speculations in the study and give it to those who will immerse themselves in more particular facts and data. We can point, however, to some areas where our hypothesis might yield testable consequences and predictions. First, one might predict that the more meritocratic a country's school system, the more likely its intellectuals are to be on the left. Second, those intellectuals who were late bloomers in school would not have developed the same sense of entidement to d1e very highest rewards; therefore, a lower percentage of the latebloomer intellectuals will be anti-capitalist than of the early bloomers. Third, we limited our hypothesis to those societies where the successful student plausibly could expect further comparable success in the wider society. In Western society, women have not heretofore plausibly held such expectations, so we would not expect the female students who constituted part of the academic upper class yet later underwent downward mobility to show the same anti-capitalist animus as male intellectuals. We might predict, then, that the more a society is known to move toward equality in occupational opportunity between women and men, the more its female intellectuals will exhibit the same disproportionate anti-capitalism its male intellectuals show. Some readers may doubt this explanation of the anti-capitalism of intellectuals. Be this as it may, I think that an important phenomenon has been identified. The sociological generalization we have stated is intuitively compelling; someiliing like it must be true. Some important effect therefore must be produced in that portion of the school's upper class d1at experiences downward social mobility, some antagonism to the wider society must get generated. If that effect is not the disproportionate opposition of the intellectuals, then what is it? We started with a puzzling phenomenon in need of an explanation. We have found, I think, an explanatory factor that is so obvious that we must believe it explains some real phenomenon. From the Publisher
HONESTY, INTELLIGENCE, AND LEFTISM ARE THREE INCOMPATIBLE THINGSby Nadia Mandarinkina, our scientific correspondent
I don't know who first noticed the leftism of intellectuals, but it's clearly not Robert Nozick who first wrote about it. Friedrich August von Hayek in his latest work The Fatal Conceit. The Error of Socialism devoted a whole chapter The Revolt of Instinct and Reason:
Hayek traces the origins of this devotion to rationalism, exaggerating the role of reason in the traditions and lists his great contemporaries, infected with socialism, including Albert Einstein. Even earlier, Ludwig von Mises wrote about this. In his work Anti-capitalistic mentality, there are sections:
✓ The Resentment of Intellectuals,
✓ Anti-capitalist Bias of American Intellectuals,
✓ The Resentment indignation of white-collar workers,
✓ The Communism of Broadway and Hollywood.
And although Mises doesn't connect how Robert Nozik, the leftism of intellectuals with the school, with education, in Human Action, he directly accuses blacksmiths of the word in spreading false, leftist ideas:
But the role of the school as a factor in the spread of leftism Mises is clearly underestimated, judging by the fact that he wrote:
I agree with Robert Nozick when he writes about the influence of the school because it coincides with my experience and observations.
I remember well how I mangled my brain to understand Marx and to deserve a good evaluation. I couldn't remember without thinking, so I had to pervert to build everything logically. My dad taught me to think logically before school.
Since at the time of my studies from foreign economic literature only a certain mainstream was accessible to us, and those of our professors who were in the West were Marxists-Communist, although advanced, I had late doubts about the scientific nature of Marxism. I remember the most difficult thing in the logic of Marxism was the proposition that the working class is the most progressive class under capitalism. The most revolutionary is permissible. But where is the progressive one? While at a seminar very famous in narrow circles Tomsk philosopher Valery B. Rodos didn't say directly that this is Marx's axiom.
After that I suddenly realized that Marx implicitly sets many of his positions as axioms, and then brilliantly proves. So for me, the scientific nature of Marxism has collapsed. Then I already read Popper, Hayek, Mises, Friedman, Kornai, Brutskus ...
But here's what I still can't understand, since you can be a left-wing intellectual? Unless exclusively for the sake of profit. After all, a man who can think, can't be left.
My Terms A left are those who believe that everything should be common. And this general must be "fairly" distributed among all.
A right are those who believe that something else can't be taken without permission.
A confused are those who believe that someone else can be taken for common good.
The capitalism is a system, an order based on the right principles.
The socialism is a system, an order based on the left principles.
The mixed economy is a system, an order based on mischievous principles.
Приглашение к обсуждению прочитанного |
Из wikipedia.orgRobert Nozick (1938 - 2002) was an American philosopher. Anarchy, State, and Utopia is a 1974 book by the American political philosopher Robert Nozick. An intellectual is a person who engages in critical thinking, research, and reflection about society and proposes solutions for its normative problems. Capitalism is an economic system and an ideology based on private ownership of the means of production and their operation for profit. Left-wing politics supports social equality and egalitarianism, often in opposition to social hierarchy and social inequality. A poet is a person who writes poetry. Novelist is an author or writer of novels, though often novelists also write in other genres of both fiction and non-fiction. Литературный критик, литератор и учёный, занимающийся литературной критикой, то есть истолкованием и оценкой преимущественно современных произведений, новых явлений и тенденций в художественной литературе с точки зрения современности, — в отличие от литературоведов, занимающихся историей и теорией литературы. A magazine journalist is a publication, usually a periodical publication, which is printed or electronically published. The mass media is a diversified collection of media technologies that reach a large audience via mass communication. A painter is a creative artist in the medium of painting. A sculptor is an artist who specializes in sculpture. A cameraman is a professional operator of a film or video camera. An academy is an institution of secondary education or higher learning, research, or honorary membership. A government is the system by which a state or community is controlled. Bureaucracy refers to both a body of non-elective government officials and an administrative policy-making group. William Butler Yeats (1865 - 1939) was an Irish poet and one of the foremost figures of 20th century literature. Thomas Stearns Eliot (1888 - 1965) was a British essayist, publisher, playwright, literary and social critic, and "one of the twentieth century's major poets". Ezra Pound (1885 - 1972) was an expatriate American poet and critic, as well as a major figure in the early modernist movement. Ludwig von Mises (1881 - 1973) was an Austrian-American theoretical Austrian School economist. Friedrich August von Hayek (1899 - 1992) was an Austrian-British economist and philosopher best known for his defense of classical liberalism. |